社科网首页 | 客户端 | 官方微博 | 报刊投稿 | 邮箱 中国社会科学网
当前位置:首页 >

constitutionalism(2)

CHAPTER II

    The Ancient Conception of a Constitution

    IN THE Oxford Dictionary, which I have long thought of as the best single

    textbook of the history of our peculiar institutions and ideas, several

    meanings of the word "constitution" are listed. It may mean the act of

    establishing or of ordaining, or the ordinance or regulation so established.

    It may mean the "make" or composition which determines the nature of

    anything, and may thus be applied to the body or the mind of man as well as

    to external objects. In the Roman Empire the word in its Latin form became

    the technical term for acts of legislation by the emperor, and from Roman

    law the Church borrowed it and applied it to ecclesiastical regulations for

    the whole Church or for some particular ecclesiastical province. From the

    Church, or possibly from the Roman lawbooks themselves, the term came back

    into use in the later middle ages as applicable to secular enactments of the

    time. In England the famous Constitutions of Clarendon of 1164 were referred

    to by Henry II and others as "constitutions," avitae constitutiones or

    leges, a recordatio vel recognitio of the relations purporting to have

    existed between church and state in the time of Henry's grandfather, Henry

    I. But in substance these were ecclesiastical provisions even though they

    were promulgated by secular authority, and this may account for the

    application to them of the word "constitutions." The word, however, is often

    found in a purely secular use at this time; though scarcely in any technical

    sense, for we find other words such as lex or edictum used interchangeably

    with constitutio for a secular administrative enactment.1 As just noted, the

    Constitutions of Clarendon are referred to in the document itself as a

    "record" (recordatio) or a "finding" (recognitio). The author of the Leges

    Henrici Primi, who wrote early in the twelfth century, soon after the

    appearance of Henry I's well-known writ for the holding of the hundred and

    county courts, also refers to that writ as a "record."2 Glanvill frequently

    uses the word "constitution" for a royal edict. He refers to Henry II's writ

    creating the remedy by grand assize as legalis ista constitutio,3 and calls

    the assize of novel disseisin both a recognitio and a constitutio.4 Bracton,

    writing a few years after the statute of Merton of 1236, calls one of its

    provisions a "new constitution,"5 and refers to a section of Magna Carta

    reissued in 1225 as constitutio libertatis.6 In France about the same time

    Beaumanoir speaks of the remedy in novel disseisin as une nouvele

    constitucion made by the kings.7

    At this time, and for centuries after, "constitution" always means a

    particular administrative enactment much as it had meant to the Roman

    lawyers. The word is used to distinguish such particular enactments from

    consuetudo or ancient custom. It is apparently never used in our modern

    sense, to denote the whole legal framework of the state. It would require a

    very detailed examination of the legal and political writings of several

    centuries to enable one to say with any confidence when this modern notion

    of a constitution first appears. I cannot claim to have made any such

    examination, but I cannot recall from my reading any clear instance of it

    before the opening of the seventeenth century. In 1578 Pierre Grégoire of

    Toulouse uses the word almost in our modern sense in his De Republica, but

    the context seems to me to indicate a somewhat wider and more general sense

    of constitutio than the strictly political meaning the word "constitution"

    now conveys, for which Grégoire seems to use the older phrase status

    reipublicae.8 The first instance given in the Oxford Dictionary of the use

    of the word "constitution" for the whole legal framework of a state is a

    phrase of Bishop Hall's in 1610, "The Constitution of the Common-wealth of

    Israel," and in my first lecture I quoted some words of Sir James

    Whitelocke's of the same year, possibly not quite so definite but even more

    striking: "the natural frame and constitution of the policy of this Kingdom,

    which is jus publicum regni."

    This use of the term "constitution" may have been new in 1610, but the idea

    it conveys is in reality one of the oldest, if not the very oldest, in the

    whole history of constitutionalism. Whitelocke's phrase which I have just

    given — "the natural frame and constitution of the policy [i.e., polity] of

    this Kingdom, which is jus publicum regni" — in reality includes two

    conceptions of a constitution closely connected and at times combined, but

    nevertheless distinct in character. One appears in Whitelocke's first words,

    "the natural frame of the state," and this idea seems as old as the politeia

    of the Greeks, which we usually translate by our word "constitution." The

    other conception is expressed by Whitelocke's other phrase, "jus publicum

    regni," the public law of the realm. The latter conception may not be as

    ancient as the former, but it is very old. Cicero, for example, voices it in

    his De Re Publica in a passage which contains the first use that I know of

    the word "constitution" in its accepted modern sense. In commending a mixed

    form of government, Cicero says, "This constitution (haec constitutio) has a

    great measure of equability without which men can hardly remain free for any

    length of time."9 Further on he says,

    "Now that opinion of Cato becomes more certain, that the

    constitution of the republic (constitutionem rei publicae) is the

    work of no single time or of no single man."10

    It is these two forms of early constitutionalism expressed by the Greek

    politeia and by the Latin constitutio, and their interrelations in history,

    that I propose to try to trace; and I shall begin with the more ancient, the

    politeia of the Greeks.

    Of all the varied meanings of which our word "constitution" is susceptible,

    the Greek politeia conforms to one of the most ancient. It means above all

    the state as it actually is. It is a term which comprises all the

    innumerable characteristics which determine that state's peculiar nature,

    and these include its whole economic and social texture as well as matters

    governmental in our narrower modern sense. It is a purely descriptive term,

    and as inclusive in its meaning as our own use of the word "constitution"

    when we speak generally of a man's constitution or of the constitution of

    matter. As Sir Paul Vinogradoff says:

    The Greeks recognized a close analogy between the

    organization of the State and the organism of the individual

    human being. They thought that the two elements of body and

    mind, the former guided and governed by the latter, had a

    parallel in two constitutive elements of the State, the rulers and

    the ruled.11

    There is nothing in the Greek language "corresponding to the Latin jus."12

    It is

    characteristic of the development of Greek juridical ideas that

    the "law of nature," though appealed to as a philosophical

    explanation of existing facts, does not serve as a means for

    concrete juridical deductions. It was at a later stage — with the

    advent of Stoicism, especially in its Roman form — that the law

    of nature began to be considered as a source of law in the

    practical sense of the term.13 In Athens there was no

    consolidated constitution.14

    The analogy between state organization and the human organism involved, as

    Mr. W. L. Newman truly says,

    that which was to a Greek the central inquiry of Political

    Science. ... It was thus that in the view of the Greeks every

    constitution had an accompanying ethos, which made itself felt in

    all the relations of life. Each constitutional form exercised a

    moulding influence on virtue; the good citizen was a different

    being in an oligarchy, a democracy, and an aristocracy. Each

    constitution embodied a scheme of life, and tended, consciously

    or not, to bring the lives of those living under it into harmony

    with its particular scheme. If the law provides that the highest

    offices in the State shall be purchasable or confines them to

    wealthy men, it inspires ipso facto a respect for wealth in the

    citizens.15

    From the Greek political classics instances almost without number might be

    given of this conception of a constitution as the ethos of a people, but I

    can mention only one or two. "Our whole state," Plato says in the Laws, "is

    an 'imitation' (mimesis) of the best and noblest life."16 In the

    Panathenaicus Isocrates says that the politeia is the "soul (psyche) of the

    polis" with power over it like that of the mind over the body;17 and

    Aristotle, in the Politics, calls it "in a sense the life of the city."18

    From this conception of the nature of the constitution, in which Greeks of

    every philosophical party seemed to share, there followed results of great

    importance both theoretical and practical.

    As Sir Paul Vinogradoff says, there is nothing in the Greek language which

    quite corresponds to the Latin word jus; and there seems to be nothing in

    the Greek conception of the state or of its constitution to correspond to

    the jus regni of Sir James Whitelocke. The Greeks made no such clear

    distinction as the Roman one between jus publicum and jus privatum; their

    politics consisted of a philosophical explanation of actual facts rather

    than a basis for concrete juridical deductions. Natural law, if admitted at

    all, became the criterion merely of the comparative excellence of a state's

    form of government; it never became for the Greeks as for the Romans the

    test of a government's legitimacy. And by the Sophists of every kind natural

    law was not admitted at all. "The tribe of Sophists," as Plato says in his

    Sophista, "is not easily caught or defined"; but the subjectivism or

    relativity that marked the philosophy of them all precluded even a

    comparison of constitutions, because it denied the existence of any values,

    or norms, or objective standards, which alone could warrant anyone in saying

    that one state's constitution was better or worse than another's. And even

    the great opponents of the Sophists, such as Plato and Aristotle, in their

    assertion of objective reality and of the possibility of man's apprehending

    it, although they believed in a universal law of nature, never went so far

    as to say that this was a coercive law. They never could have said as Cicero

    did, that states have no power through senate or people to free themselves

    from it.19 Natural law meant to them, as to the modern scientist, no more

    than the fact of invariability. It carried with it no notion of sanction.

    One of the clearest statements of this Greek attitude toward the fundamental

    relations of government to law is to be found in the Politicus or Statesman

    of Plato, a dialogue whose central theme is the problem of

    "constitutionalism" — of all Plato's dialogues the one most directly

    concerned with the subject we have now in hand. I have long felt that this

    dialogue, though less fundamental, no doubt, than the Republic, has been too

    much neglected in our estimate of Plato's real political position and

    purpose; and not of his own position alone, but of the normal attitude

    toward constitutionalism in the Academy and the Lyceum at least, if not in

    Greece generally.

    It was mainly with this work, rather than with the Republic, Professor

    Jaeger insists, that Aristotle's study of Plato's political doctrines was

    concerned,20 and he shows conclusively throughout his remarkable book how

    vitally important that study was in forming the political conception which

    Aristotle held to the very end. "He had accepted Plato's doctrines with his

    whole soul," Professor Jaeger says, "and the effort to discover his own

    relation to them occupied all his life, and is the clue to his

    development."21

    The central question discussed in the Politicus is the perennial one of the

    proper relation of government to law. Plato has been claimed as a fellow by

    some of the modern proponents of the totalitarian state, but how anyone

    could honestly make such a claim after he had carefully pondered the

    Politicus is wholly beyond my comprehension. If one should disregard Plato's

    plain statements of his purpose in the Republic, it is perhaps conceivable

    that one might distort that dialogue into a defense of actual arbitrary

    governments; yet the whole discussion in the Politicus plainly shows that

    this is not Plato's true position but the very antithesis of it.

    It is true that even in the Politicus the defects of constitutional

    governments are clearly recognized. In fact they are probably stated with

    greater distinctness in this dialogue than in any other of the Platonic

    writings. Constitutional government, Plato admits, is to be regarded only as

    a "second best" (os deuteron as compared with to proton). But the "first" or

    best type of political relations, a government unhampered by law, is, he

    declares unequivocally, only an ideal of which actual states can never be

    more than an approximation, and usually not a very close approximation.

    Limitations of law always do hamper government; and, provided the government

    is a good one, there may be good things that such a government can achieve,

    if unrestricted, which these limitations of law render impossible of

    accomplishment.

    The problem that Plato faces here is a practical one that is likely to

    persist as long as government itself. A constitutional government will

    always be a weak government when compared with an arbitrary one. There will

    be many desirable things, as well as undesirable, which are easy for a

    despotism but impossible elsewhere. Constitutionalism suffers from the

    defects inherent in its own merits. Because it cannot do some evil it is

    precluded from doing some good. Shall we, then, forego the good to prevent

    the evil, or shall we submit to the evil to secure the good? This is the

    fundamental practical question of all constitutionalism. It is the foremost

    issue in the present political world; and it is amazing, and to many of us

    very alarming, to consider to what insufferable barbarities nation after

    nation today is showing a willingness to submit, for the recompense it

    thinks it is getting or hopes to get from an arbitrary government. This

    great problem is the central one in Plato's dialogue, and Plato's answer to

    it cannot but interest the present-day reformer as well as the historian of

    constitutional development.

    That answer is based on the fundamental distinction, but at the same time

    the very close connection, sometimes overlooked or underestimated, between

    the ideal on the one hand and the actual or the attainable. Plato's Republic

    deals with an unattainable ideal; his Politicus treats of the attainable in

    its relation to this, same ideal. The attainable is less perfect than the

    ideal, and it is the presence of legal restriction that makes it so; for

    law, as Plato says, is

    like an obstinate and ignorant tyrant who will not allow anything

    to be done contrary to his appointment or any question to be

    asked — not even in sudden changes of circumstances, when

    something happens to be better than what he commanded for

    some one.

    The law cannot comprehend exactly what is noblest or more

    just, or at once ordain what is best, for all. The differences of

    men and actions, and the endless irregular movements of human

    things, do not admit of any universal and simple rule. No art can

    lay down any rule which will last forever.

    A perfectly simple principle can never be applied to a state of

    things which is the reverse of simple.

    How familiar these objections to constitutionalism sound! Their burden is

    always the present insufficiency of law inherited from some "horse and

    buggy" era in the past. And of course no one could deny the validity of such

    objections. There is a practical recognition of them in the history of our

    equitable remedies for the deficiencies of rigid legal rules, and the

    entrusting to governments of a discretionary power in exceptional cases to

    dispense with law or to pardon a breach of it necessarily implies the

    admission that this law, especially if it is an ancient law, can never

    secure adequate justice in every particular case. The principal defect of

    all law is at the same time its most essential and most valuable

    characteristic — its generality.

    It was considerations such as these that led Plato to hold that the best

    government theoretically or ideally is one based upon the discretion of the

    ruler and not upon law; and such a government conforms precisely to the

    meaning of our word "despotism" — in this case a perfectly benevolent

    despotism, of course. So he asks:

    As the pilot watches over the interests of the ship, or of the

    crew, and preserves the lives of his fellow sailors, not by laying

    down rules, but by making his art a law — even so, and in the

    self-same way, may there not be a true form of polity created by

    those who are able to govern in a similar spirit, and who show a

    strength of art which is superior to the law?22

    From this sentence it is evident, as it is from the whole tenor of the

    dialogue, that the ideally best rule exists where the ruler is not limited

    by law but makes his art a law. But another thing is equally evident here

    and equally prominent throughout the Politicus, namely, that this "art" of

    the ruler shows "a strength of art which is superior to the law." This

    brings up the final and most crucial question of all. Is Plato in this

    dialogue insisting on the superiority of despotism over constitutionalism as

    a principle of practical politics, or is he trying to illustrate the very

    opposite? To put it more concretely, does Plato believe in the actual or

    possible existence of any ruler with such "strength of art" that his "art"

    should be the only law of the state? He evidently believes such a

    philosopher-king ought to rule as a despot if you could only find him. But

    does he believe that such an incomparable embodiment of omniscience,

    omnicompetence, and utter benevolence could possibly exist except in the

    imagination? It is interesting to note the historical tendency of peoples

    generally to deify their rulers once they have conceded despotic authority

    to them. A divine competence in a ruler is in fact the only real

    justification of a despotism; and where there is despotism the apotheosis of

    the ruler is likely sooner or later to appear in some form. It is

    interesting but not strange to find Cardinal Ballarmine in the sixteenth

    century arguing that the Church should have a despotic government because

    the Church is divine, while the state ought to have a limited government

    because the state is human. The answer to the question whether Plato was

    politically an absolutist or a constitutionalist depends then on the answer

    to another: Did Plato believe that his philosopher-king had appeared or

    could possibly appear in any actual state on earth? Through what seems to me

    a misinterpretation of the Republic, some have attributed the latter view to

    Plato, but the whole argument of the Politicus is against it; and I cannot

    agree with those who find in the Politicus inconsistency with the Republic

    or a contradiction of it. Like Cardinal Ballarmine, and on much the same

    general grounds, Plato regarded absolute government as the only celestial

    one and celestial government as the only one properly absolute.

    A godlike ruler should rule like a god, and if a godlike man should appear

    among men, godlike rule would and should be gladly conceded to him. This was

    Aristotle's view, and he may well have got it from the teachings of Plato.

    But I know of nothing in all Plato's writings which indicates a belief in

    the actual, or even the possible, existence of a superman like this; and

    without such a demigod despotism becomes for Plato, not the best, but the

    worst of all possible governments. Between these two extremes lay his

    second-best state under constitutional rule. It is of little consequence

    that there should be one ruler, or a few or many rulers, in such a state,

    provided the government be limited by law; and, in the cases where it is so

    limited, Plato finds an approximation of the "art" of the perfect despot

    close enough to warrant him in speaking of monarchy, aristocracy, and a

    constitutional democracy as forms of government, sadly defective indeed, but

    true; in comparison with the three corresponding perverted forms, in all of

    which men totally devoid of any "strength of art" superior to the law — the

    only justification of despotism — have nevertheless made their own art the

    state's sole law.

    It may seem a paradox, if not even worse, to say, as Plato does here, that

    actual despotisms are less closely akin to the ideal despotism than these

    constitutional governments which at first sight seem so much less like it.

    But to Plato it is not the external form of a state that differentiates it

    from another, but the guiding inner principle of its political life, above

    all the presence or absence of justice. In a constitutional government the

    laws under which the state is ruled are far inferior to the wisdom of the

    perfect ruler, chiefly on account of their rigidity; but these laws are none

    the less "imitations" (mimemata) of that perfect wisdom — very faulty

    "copies" of the government of the ideal state. They are copies, and copies

    which to Plato embody a greater measure of true justice than the arbitrary

    will of vicious or ignorant men can ever do; and even the best of men are

    more or less vicious and ignorant. Law, as Aristotle says, is "intelligence

    without passion."23

    For the subject with which we are immediately concerned — constitutionality

    in its actual rather than its ideal form — the Politicus seems to disclose

    Plato's real opinions more clearly than his description of omniscient

    despotism in the unattainable ideal of the Republic. If the Politicus gives

    us a true picture of its author's mind, he was certainly no advocate of

    arbitrary government in the actual political world. In this dialogue he does

    not explain at length just why he thinks national custom a safer guide than

    the fiat of government, but he gives unmistakable evidence that he does

    think so. His preference for the Rechtsstaat may have been mainly pragmatic.

    In the Laws he notes that all other states are "on the highway to ruin,"24

    and appeals to that right reason "which the law affirms, and which the

    experience of the best of our elders has agreed to be truly right."25 But

    whatever the grounds for it may have been, his belief in the superiority of

    law over will as a principle of actual government can hardly be doubted.

    If then the Politicus gives a true indication of Plato's political beliefs,

    and if my hurried summary of it is not inaccurate, there is little comfort

    to be derived from him by believers in totalitarianism.

    One further point alone I can stop to note about his constitutionalism. In

    common with Socrates and Aristotle and in opposition to the Sophists, he

    believed in a universal norm of political life to be apprehended through

    human reason or "nature," by which the various forms of polity may be judged

    and compared; and this norm might be roughly termed a "law of nature." But

    there is one striking difference between the conception of a "law of nature"

    as he held it — and as did apparently all his Greek contemporaries of every

    party — and the one later transmitted by the Stoics to Rome. The law of

    nature is to him no more than a basis of comparison. He thinks of this law,

    as he thinks of all law, merely as an intellectual standard. Law is nothing

    more than the uniformity of nature, and human law is likewise nothing but

    the common apprehension of a part of this uniformity by man. It is thus a

    common "yardstick" by which one form of polity may be compared on its merits

    with another, and even one enactment made within a state with another. The

    latter is the distinction between true law in the abstract (nomos) and

    particular laws (nomizomena), dealt with in the Platonic dialogue Minos —

    Platonic whether by Plato or not. Such particular laws are good when they

    embody the true law and not otherwise.

    But with this comparison of polities or of laws Greek constitutionalism of

    the classical period seems to stop. It goes no further than mere

    intellectual assessment or comparison. It may pronounce that a given polity

    or particular law is bad; it does not go on to say it is not binding. It may

    even say that these bad enactments are not true law at all, but it does not

    say they can be disregarded. As Rehm observes, the customary definition of

    the state was not a legal definition at all, but a political one;26 the

    ancient theorists were concerned primarily with an "ethico-political

    appraisal of the relations between the state and other forms of human

    association," 27 not with the "sovereignty" which bulks so large in all

    modern discussions of political relations. Aristotle's word for the

    supremacy in a state corresponding to our "sovereignty," to kyrion, does not

    imply supreme constituted authority, as sovereignty does, but a supremacy in

    fact only.28 In short, the conception of constitutionalism based on the

    notion of law prevailing generally in this period is of a constitution in

    the primitive sense noted above, of the whole nature or "composure" of a

    thing. Such a conception of law may warrant one in saying that a particular

    enactment is bad, but never that it is not legitimate. There is no room

    under such a conception for any distinction such as we make between a

    provision that is binding because constitutional and one that is void for

    unconstitutionality. What this amounts to is that "the law of the

    constitution," if we might employ such a phrase, is not coercive but only

    normative; and that constitutions have no sanction in our modern sense.

    Whatever the phrase "an unconstitutional law" might have meant for Plato or

    for Aristotle, if he had ever used it, it would never have meant a law void

    on account of unconstitutionality; and, while a "constitutional law" might

    conceivably have meant one concerned with the framework of the state, it

    could never have been a "fundamental" law in our sense of that phrase.

    The difference just noted between our notion of constitutionality and the

    antique one is only one aspect of the difference between the modern and the

    ancient view of the state in general. Before the Stoics, Greeks apparently

    drew no clear distinction between society and the state, between the social

    and the civil. But institutions that are thus identical must also be coeval.

    Potentially at least, the state must therefore be as old as human

    association, there is no science of society apart from politics, and there

    can be no natural law older than the laws of actual states. As a

    consequence, the Greeks thought of the law in a state only as one part or

    rather as one aspect of the whole polity itself, never as something outside

    or apart from the state to which that polity must conform, nor even as any

    special provision within the state to which other laws are subordinate. If

    the Greeks thought of a law of nature as applying to a particular state at

    all, they meant by this natural law no more than that portion of a state's

    actual laws which in fact happens to be identical in all other states — what

    Aristotle in his Rhetoric called "common law" (koinos nomos);29 they had in

    mind no "fundamental" principles which must invalidate a municipal law

    inconsistent with them; in short, they thought of law in terms of the state,

    not of the state in terms of law, as the Roman and the medieval man

    invariably did. It was only after the appearance of a notion of a higher and

    an older law, out of which the laws of particular states are fashioned and

    to which they must conform in order to be valid, that the modern conception

    of constitutionalism could replace the ancient one. The change, however, has

    come when Cicero can define a state as a bond of law (vinculum juris); for

    here by law he means no law of the state itself, but an antecedent law, and

    one antecedent in time as well as sanction. He says expressly in his De Re

    Publica that this law is as old as the mind of God, existing long before

    there were any states in the world. But more important still, he adds that

    no state can ever enact any binding law in derogation of this law of nature,

    a statement that no Greek of the fifth or fourth century B.C. could have

    dreamt of making, even supposing that he could have understood it. There is

    probably no change in the whole history of political theory more

    revolutionary than this, and certainly none so momentous for the future of

    constitutionalism. From this great difference between the ancient and the

    modern conception of constitutionalism some very important practical results

    may be traced. Since, under the older conception, the politeia, or

    constitution as we may call it, included not merely a jus publicum regni but

    the whole life of the state, two or three great practical differences

    between ancient and modern states seem to be logically incident to it,

    differences that even a slight comparison of ancient and modern

    constitutional history clearly discloses. First, in the ancient regime there

    is no remedy for an unconstitutional act short of actual revolution.

    Secondly, such revolution, when it occurs, is usually no mere modification

    of the "public law," such as Whitelocke's jus publicum regni, but a complete

    overturn of the state's institutions, a change in its whole way of life. It

    is a social as well as a merely "political" revolution in our modern

    narrower sense of "political." Aristotle refers to such revolutions as a

    dissolution of the polities in which they occur; the "constitutions" and

    with them the states themselves are destroyed, or rather, actually

    "dissolved" (lyontai).30 Thirdly, it is this fundamental and far-reaching

    character of most actual revolutions in Greece, in so many cases touching

    everything in the state, social, economic, and intellectual, as well as

    governmental; changes usually carried out by violence, proscription,

    ostracism, and even death, in ways very similar to the proceedings so

    familiar to us in parts of Europe today and with much the same underlying

    causes — it is this wholesale character of so many contemporary revolutions

    that accounts for the Greek fear of stasis and the nervous desire to risk

    almost anything that might prevent it. For stasis is a lack of equilibrium,

    a condition of disharmony in a state, which is almost sure to entail unrest

    and eventual revolution with all its usual horrors. Nothing less than such

    revolution and the constant dread of its results could have led Aristotle,

    for example, to advise tyrants how to prolong a type of government which he

    admits to be the most oppressive in the world as well as the shortest-lived;

    and Aristotle's attitude toward stasis indicated in the Politics is

    reflected in most of the political writings surviving from Aristotle's time

    in Greece. The Greek states were notoriously unstable, and this situation

    led to a desire to preserve the status quo which to us seems at times almost

    reactionary. The analysis that Aristotle gives of the causes of sedition is

    as keen as the remedies are often cynical. One has to pinch himself to

    realize that he is not reading from some resume of recent events in Europe

    when, for example, Aristotle says:

    It is as little possible to create a state in any arbitrary period of

    time as to create it of any arbitrary population. Accordingly the

    great majority of states to which a number of alien colonists have

    been admitted at the time of their foundation, or at a later date,

    have been the scenes of violent sedition.31

    Or this:

    Polities generally are liable to dissolution not only from within but

    from without, when there is a state having an antagonistic polity

    near to them or distant but possessed of considerable power.32

    Or take the following summary he gives of the measures usually adopted and

    actually necessary to preserve a tyranny:

    The practice of cutting off prominent characters and putting out

    of the way the high spirits in the state; the prohibition of common

    meals, political clubs, high culture and everything else of the

    same kind; precautionary measures against all that tends to

    produce two results, viz., spirit and confidence; the opposition

    offered to literary reunions or any other meetings of a literary

    kind, and the endeavor by every possible means to produce the

    greatest mutual ignorance among all the citizens, as it is

    acquaintance that tends to produce mutual confidence.33

    "Another expedient," he says,

    is the endeavor to prevent any word or action of any subject

    from escaping detection by a system of spies. ... For the citizens

    are then less free of speech for fear of the spies and, if they do

    speak freely, are more easily discovered.34

    And, he adds,

    A tyrant is fond of making wars, as a means of keeping his

    subjects in employment and in continual need of a

    commander.35

    The sum of all such measures, Aristotle concludes, is "to prevent mutual

    confidence among the citizens, to incapacitate them for action, and to

    degrade their spirit."36

    From these notions of constitutionalism prevailing in ancient Greece which I

    have been trying to summarize, we must proceed next to the character of the

    changes which made such notions so radically different when we first meet

    them among the Romans some three centuries later; and this change in

    constitutionalism seems to be bound up with a change in the definition of

    natural law, which must be briefly indicated before the beginnings of Roman

    or medieval constitutionalism themselves can be made clear.